Reconstructing Dewey: The Philosophy of Critical Pragmatism

Polity . Volume 38, Number 4 . October 2006 r 2006 Northeastern Political Science Association 0032-3497/06 $30.00 www.palgrave-journals.com/polity ...
Author: Mervyn Collins
0 downloads 1 Views 144KB Size
Polity

. Volume 38, Number 4 . October 2006

r 2006 Northeastern Political Science Association 0032-3497/06 $30.00 www.palgrave-journals.com/polity

Reconstructing Dewey: The Philosophy of Critical Pragmatism Alison Kadlec Public Agenda, New York The historical relationship between pragmatism and critical theory is one in which the antifoundational and practice-oriented dimensions of pragmatism appear to exist in tension, if not outright conflict, with the emancipatory commitments of the neo-Marxist legacy of critical theory. While Deweyan pragmatism is most often understood in its deliberative, experimental, open-ended, and contextual dimensions, little attention has been paid to the critical dimensions of Dewey’s thought. In what follows, I take the initial steps in recovering the critical features of Dewey’s pragmatism by developing my analysis along two lines. First, I sketch the general contours of the relationship between pragmatism and critical theory in order to account for and unpack the long-standing hostility of critical theorists toward pragmatism. Second, I argue that these hostilities are unwarranted, and that they have been passed to us in the form of a persistent inability to appreciate the critical features of Dewey’s pragmatism. Through an investigation of the philosophical underpinnings of Dewey’s pragmatism, I hope to show that Dewey’s democratic commitments to the transformatory potential of lived experience, to a reconstructed conception of individualism, and to the cultivation of reflective social intelligence might be viewed as the basis of a critical theory worthy of greater attention and appreciation. Moreover, I hope that this effort will open avenues of inquiry into what might be called a model of ‘‘critical pragmatism.’’ Polity (2006) 38, 519–542. doi:10.1057/palgrave.polity.2300067

Keywords

Dewey; pragmatism; critical theory

Alison Kadlec is a Senior Research Associate at the nonprofit public interest/ public engagement research organization Public Agenda in New York City. She is the author of a book on Dewey’s Critical Pragmatism to be published by Lexington Books, a division of Rowman and Littlefield. The author can be reached at www.publicagenda.org.

520

CRITICAL PRAGMATISM

‘‘In dethroning our absolutes, we must take care not to exile our imperatives, for after all, we live by them.’’ —Alain Locke1 This paper joins a broad discussion of the relationship between John Dewey’s pragmatism and the tradition of critical theory.2 In general terms, the historical relationship between pragmatism and critical theory is one in which the antifoundational and practice-oriented dimensions of pragmatism appear to exist in tension, if not outright conflict, with the emancipatory commitments of critical theory’s neo-Marxist legacy. While Deweyan pragmatism is most often understood in its deliberative, experimental, open-ended, and contextual dimensions, little attention has been paid to the critical dimensions of Dewey’s thought. In what follows, I take initial steps in recovering the critical features of Dewey’s pragmatism by developing an analysis along two lines. First, I sketch the general contours of the relationship between pragmatism and critical theory in order to account for and unpack the long-standing hostility of critical theorists toward pragmatism. Second, I argue that these hostilities are unwarranted, and that they have been passed to us in the form of a persistent inability of critical theorists to appreciate the more radical features of Dewey’s pragmatism. In contrast to the prevailing characterizations of pragmatism, I argue that the philosophical underpinnings of Dewey’s pragmatism form the core of an enterprise which is both antifoundational and critical. Moreover, I hope that this effort will open avenues of inquiry into what might be called a model of ‘‘critical pragmatism.’’3 1. Alain Locke, ‘‘Values and Imperatives,’’ in The Philosophy of Alain Locke, ed. Leonard Harris (Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press, 1935). 2. It is certainly because of Ju¨rgen Habermas’s attraction to American pragmatism, particularly that of Charles Sanders Peirce and George Herbert Mead, that interest in the relationship between the two traditions has emerged in recent years. See Mitchell Aboulafia, Myra Bookman, and Katherine Kemp, ed., Habermas and Pragmatism (London: Routledge Press, 2002). 3. Although Dewey himself never used the phrase ‘‘critical pragmatism,’’ chap. 10 of Experience and Nature (LW1: 295–326) is dedicated to delineating the relationship between ‘‘existence, value, and criticism.’’ In this chapter, Dewey argues that criticism begins as reflective analysis, which in turn forms the basis of philosophy. The argument is rich and complex and, though Experience and Nature is not the subject of my effort here, deep engagement with this work, along with The Quest for Certainty (LW4) would be required for any comprehensive treatment of the critical dimensions of Dewey’s pragmatism. The actual phrase ‘‘critical pragmatism’’ appears at least as early as 1935 in Alain Locke’s pragmatic theory of valuation. In the context of Locke’s work, the idea of a critical pragmatism was supposed to undergird the development of cultural pluralism. Although Locke’s work has received scant attention, it should be noted that much of his work in the context of the Harlem Renaissance was grounded in his reading of Dewey, and his having studied with James. See Johnny Washington, Alain Locke and Philosophy: A Quest for Cultural Pluralism (Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1986). More recently, however, the idea of a critical pragmatism as well as a pragmatist critical theory has begun to receive new attention. See Dmitir Shalin, ‘‘Critical Theory and the Pragmatist Challenge,’’ American Journal of Sociology 98 (September 1992); Steven K. White, The Cambridge Companion to Habermas (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1995); James Farr, ‘‘John Dewey and American Political Science,’’ American

Alison Kadlec

521

In an article for the new Cambridge Companion to Critical Theory, Stephen K. White becomes the most recent contributor to the burgeoning field of inquiry into the relationship between pragmatism and critical theory. White argues that, if appropriately revised, the early critical theory of the Frankfurt School provides a sound philosophical basis for a critical social science. This revision proceeds in two directions; Habermas’s model of ‘‘communicative rationality’’ is an internal source, while the deliberative properties of pragmatism serve as an external source for this productive revision of critical theory. As a point of departure, I begin with White’s claim that pragmatism does not, in and of itself, contain the substance required to count among the legitimate approaches to social science. According to White, while pragmatism may help to revitalize critical theory, it does not constitute a coherent tradition of social criticism. As a social philosophy based on multiplicity and contingency, pragmatism is merely an ‘‘ethos’’ containing ‘‘some minimal direction and sensibility.’’4 This ethos, says White, requires the fortification of a more forcefully normative research tradition in order to gain the ‘‘necessary substance to stand as an adequate approach.’’5 Because pragmatism is ‘‘problem-driven,’’ it has, since its resurrection by Richard Rorty in the late 1970s, been consistently deployed in ways that are ‘‘decidedly unsuspicious about structures of power.’’6 For White, this apparent blindness to issues of power seems a natural accompaniment to the antifoundational, associational, and perspectival ethos of pragmatism. In short, pragmatism cannot be viewed as a critical tradition because one cannot adopt an antifoundational stance and still cultivate a guiding focus on power relations and structures of inequality. Although I agree with White that pragmatism benefits enormously from being placed in dialogic relation with critical theory, I argue that there is another way to frame the political relevance of this dialogue. Despite the growing interest in the relationship between pragmatism and critical theory, remarkably scant attention has been paid to the historical dimensions of this relationship. Although Dewey never explicitly discussed the work of critical theorists, there exists a long history of hostility toward pragmatism Journal of Political Science 43 (April 1999); and ‘‘Engels, Dewey, and Marxism in America,’’ in Engels After Marx, ed. Manfred Steger and Terrell Carver (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1999). All references to Dewey, with the exception of Democracy and Education are to the collected works, published in three sets. The Collected Works of John Dewey, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 1967–1972). The Early Works, 1882–1889 (EW, 5 volumes); The Middle Works, 1899–1824 (MW, 15 volumes); The Later Works, 1925-1953 (LW, 17 volumes). 4. White, Cambridge Companion, 314. 5. White, Cambridge Companion, 314. 6. It is generally accepted that with the 1979 publication of Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Rorty single-handedly revived interest in Dewey by arguing that along with Heidegger and Wittgenstein, Dewey ‘‘is one of the three most important philosophers of the twentieth century,’’ in Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979), 5.

522

CRITICAL PRAGMATISM

on the part of critical theorists and their predecessors. Beginning with Gramsci and extending through the Frankfurt School, there has long been a perceived affinity between pragmatism and positivism, which forms the core of critical neo-Marxist rejections of pragmatism.7 I argue that there is little hope of fully appreciating the critical dimensions of Dewey’s pragmatism without first understanding the consequences that have followed from the specious association of pragmatism and positivism. Specifically, by erroneously equating Dewey’s celebration of lived experience and a scientific worldview with a vulgar glorification of all things given, the early critical theorists shut off access to an innovative and deeply critical component of Deweyan pragmatism.8 In his well-known summary of the basic principles of critical theory, Raymond Geuss says, ‘‘critical theories have special standing as guides for human action’’ because (1) they aim at producing enlightened individuals capable of identifying their own real interests; (2) they are inherently emancipatory, particularly in their attention to the ways humans unwittingly participate in creating the conditions for their own oppression; and (3) their ‘‘reflective’’ epistemological stance stands in contrast to the ‘‘objectifying’’ epistemology of the natural sciences.9 Although it is not my purpose to demonstrate definitively that Dewey’s pragmatism is an ‘‘authentic’’ critical theory, my approach here is aimed at helping us rethink the perceived epistemological variance between critical theory and pragmatism. Through an investigation of the philosophical underpinnings of Dewey’s pragmatism, I hope to show that Dewey’s epistemological commitment to the transformatory potential of lived experience, to ‘‘growth as the only moral end,’’ and to the cultivation of reflective social intelligence might be viewed as the basis of a critical theory worthy of greater attention and appreciation. My historical reconstruction is, in other words, aimed at narrowing the epistemological gap 7. For a related discussion. see Chaps. 3 and 4 of Hans Joas, Pragmatism and Social Theory (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993), 79–125. 8. It is important to make clear from the outset that ‘‘experience’’ connotes a very specific, although rather complicated, constellation of ideas. Although he explored many different kinds of experience (e.g. aesthetic experience, cognitive experience, and religious experience), there are red threads that run throughout his multifarious use of the term. Most simply, ‘‘experience’’ in Dewey’s lexicon means two specific things. First, in contrast to the traditional conception of experience as a matter of individual consciousness, Dewey’s notion of experience is intersubjective, communicative, and social. As Dewey says, ‘‘Experience is no slipping along in a path fixed by inner consciousness. Private consciousness is an incidental outcome of experience of a vital objective sort; it is not its source.’’ Second, experience is a matter of ‘‘enduring’’ and ‘‘undergoing’’ the consequences of our actions, and is therefore best understood as an ongoing process. Taken together, these ideas form the basis of a powerful resource for critical reflection and social transformation. In Dewey’s social philosophy, lived experience is a tool for meaningful democratic struggle to the extent that it consists of a critical and forward-thinking perception of the private and shared consequences of our actions. See Dewey’s ‘‘The Need for a Recovery of Philosophy,’’ MW10. 9. Raymond Geuss, The Idea of a Critical Theory: Habermas and the Frankfurt School (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1981), 1–2.

Alison Kadlec

523

between the commitments of critical theorists and the antifoundational celebration of science that undergirds Dewey’s pragmatism. After tracing the historical dimensions of the relationship between pragmatism and critical theory, I will return to Dewey’s own understanding of the critical purpose of philosophy and social inquiry. Reconstruction in Philosophy (1920) is an ideal locus for this investigation for both historical and practical reasons. The broad historical sweep of the work makes it an excellent introduction to Dewey’s pragmatism in a broad context.10 Aside from the fact that Reconstruction in Philosophy is one of Dewey’s most historically perspicuous and philosophically focused works, it also happens to be the repository of ideas subjected to the most scathing attack by the Frankfurt School theorists.11 As the explicit subject of Max Horkheimer’s assault on pragmatism in Eclipse of Reason (1947), Dewey’s understanding of ‘‘reconstruction’’ must be defended as an intrinsically critical concept against Horkheimer’s identification of pragmatism with vulgar positivism.12 For Dewey, reconstruction is the name given to the work we do when we apply creative intelligence to rethinking and readjusting our principles and practices. In Reconstruction in Philosophy, Dewey engages in a historical analysis of the development of Western philosophy in order to reconstruct its potential for informing democratic struggle. Although Dewey was a great admirer of the Greek contributions to philosophy, he argued that Plato and Aristotle were, each in his own way, to blame for many of the persistent shortcomings of Western philosophy.13 Dewey’s reconstruction of philosophy focuses to a large extent on exposing and dismantling the Ancient Greek bifurcation of reason and experience in order to recover the power of everyday lived experience to fund critical reflection or reason. This reconstruction, I argue, lends itself to misunderstanding because it is grounded in Dewey’s unabashed admiration of science. By turning my attention to the impact of Darwin on Dewey’s thought, I hope to demonstrate that Dewey’s approach to science belies any sharp epistemological distinction that one might be tempted to draw between genuine reflection and scientific inquiry. Moreover, I argue that Dewey’s intersubjective and dynamic conception of experience is 10. Although Reconstruction in Philosophy is a relatively short book, Dewey essentially surveys the history of Western philosophy from the Ancients to the Enlightenment. These broad strokes are helpful in creating a macrocosmic picture of his general approach to pragmatism in philosophical terms. All references to Reconstruction in Philosophy are found in Middle Works (MW12). 11. Horkheimer’s attack is grounded in his creative reading of Dewey’s 1917 reflections in ‘‘A Recovery in Philosophy,’’ the short essay which prefigures the themes developed in Reconstruction in Philosophy (MW10). 12. For an excellent discussion of Horkheimer’s conflating of positivism and pragmatism, see Hans Joas, ‘‘An Underestimated Alternative: America and the Limits of Critical Theory,’’ in Pragmatism and Social Theory (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993), 79–93. 13. In addition to Reconstruction in Philosophy, Dewey’s most sustained discussions of classical philosophy are located in The Quest for Certainty (LW4) and the shorter ‘‘The ‘Socratic Dialogues’ of Plato’’ (LW2).

524

CRITICAL PRAGMATISM

itself a critical construct that can be deployed in the service of meaningful social struggle. Realizing the potential of everyday experience as a definitive source of critical reflection and democratic struggle requires a reconstruction of the notion of ‘‘individualism’’ that Dewey’s idea of ‘‘growth’’ makes possible.14 Although lived experience is, in and of itself, not necessarily a resource for critical reflection, Dewey argues that the critical potential of experience can and must be tapped if we are to mount an effective challenge to entrenched interests and actualize our democratic commitments to liberty and equality of opportunity. This realization of potential, however, first requires a dedication to reconstructing our understanding of individualism.15 Therefore, in the last section here, I turn to Individualism Old and New (1929) and argue that Dewey advances a profoundly critical notion of individualism that is based on his unique conceptions of experience, growth, and social intelligence. In order to pave the way for an examination of this nexus between experience as critical reflection, growth as reconstructed individualism, and social intelligence as the fodder for democratic struggle as key components of Dewey’s critical pragmatism, I begin here by tracing key historical dimensions of the relationship between critical theory and pragmatism. As Hans Joas has noted, this history is one of ‘‘misunderstandings, deliberate distortions, and well-meaning incomprehension.’’16

Pragmatism and the Politics of Positivism: from Gramsci to the Frankfurt School The early critical theory of the Frankfurt School may be viewed as the second generation of critical neo-Marxism, a strain of Marxist thought that has its direct 14. I place these words in quotes because they are complex ideas that Dewey characteristically defines against the grain of ordinary usage. 15. It should be noted that my focus here on lived experience and reconstructed individualism, while sufficiently robust for my purposes, only captures two aspects of a far more comprehensive, complex, and expansive system that comprises Dewey’s philosophical worldview. For a more complete understanding of this larger framework, one must engage a number of works Dewey produced in the 1920s, including, in addition to Reconstruction in Philosophy, both Experience and Nature (LW1) and The Quest for Certainty (LW4). 16. Although there is not a great deal of literature on this subject, Hans Joas’s article on the relationship between German thought and American pragmatism in Pragmatism and Social Theory has cleared the ground for my approach. Although my focus here is quite distinct from Joas’s, there are two notable commonalities: First, like Joas’s, my discussion is aimed at illuminating the persistently overlooked theoretical common ground shared by critical theory and pragmatism. More specifically, both Joas and I discuss the particular impact of Horkheimer’s rejection of pragmatism in The Eclipse of Reason. Although we take different approaches, and therefore cover quite distinct terrain, Joas’s contributions form an important backdrop for the specific trajectory I trace here. See Hans Joas, ‘‘American Pragmatism and German Thought: A History of Misunderstandings,’’ in his Pragmatism and Social Theory (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993), 94–121.

Alison Kadlec

525

antecedents in the work of, among others, Gramsci.17 From Gramsci, the early Frankfurt School theorists inherited the kernel of their hostility toward pragmatism. It is within his construction of the ‘‘philosophy of praxis’’ that Gramsci first takes aim at pragmatism, thus setting the stage for the subsequent interpretations of pragmatism as a crude apology for the status quo. For Gramsci, philosophy should be viewed as a social activity in which all people are implicitly engaged. ‘‘All men are philosophers,’’ he argues, because in ‘‘even the slightest manifestation of any intellectual activity whatever, in ‘language,’ there is contained a specific conception of the world.’’ Since we are in fact always living some conception of the world, the question becomes, ‘‘is it better to take part in a conception of the world mechanically imposed by the external environment . . . or, on the other hand, is it better to work out consciously and critically one’s own conception of the world and thus, take an active part in the creation of the history of the world?’’18 Because one’s conception of the world is a response to certain specific problems posed by life as we experience it, the goal of the philosophy of praxis is to dissociate these problems from the hegemonic realm of ‘‘common sense,’’ and subject them instead to the critico-practical activity of philosophy properly conceived. Gramsci cautions that the critico-practical nature of the philosophy of praxis must not be confused with the practical spirit of pragmatism, although he finds this spirit praiseworthy. In short, it is in contrast to the merely practical approach of pragmatism that Gramsci advances his properly practical understanding of philosophy as political action.19

17. In addition to Gramsci, Lukacs and Korsch were the most notable figures who shared in the revival of German idealism at this time. Although Korsch and Lukacs made significant contributions in the struggles against determinist and positivist interpretations of historical materialism, it was Gramsci’s ‘‘philosophy of praxis’’ that most fully embodied the aims of this first phase of critical Marxism. For discussions of the theoretical and political problems plaguing both Lukacs’s and Korsch’s careers as critical Marxists, see Martin Jay’s classic Dialectical Imagination: A History of the Frankfurt School (Boston: Little, Brown, 1973), and Andrew Arato, ‘‘Political Sociology and the Critique of Politics,’’ in The Essential Frankfurt School Reader, ed. Andrew Arato and Eike Gebhardt (New York: Urizen Books, 1978). 18. Antonio Gramsci, Selections from the Prison Notebooks, trans. Quinton Hoare and Geoffrey Nowell (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1971), 321. 19. This is perhaps the area in which Gramsci’s misunderstanding of pragmatism is at its most acute, because his understanding of common sense is deeply akin to pragmatic treatments of the idea of ‘‘habit.’’ For example, Gramsci’s understanding of common sense as a ‘‘collective noun’’ is not unlike William James understanding of ‘‘habit’’ as the ‘‘enormous fly-wheel of society.’’ Both ideas denote those thought patterns that allow for the continual reproduction of existing values and institutions in the absence of critical reflection. As a consequence, Gramsci’s contrasting concept of ‘‘good sense’’ is very similar to Dewey’s reconstructed understanding of ‘‘habits’’ as the flexible patterns of thought and action generated according to the sorts of critical ruminations that work to continually undo ‘‘common sense’’ in the Gramscian sense of the word. For James’s discussion of habit, see the chapter entitled ‘‘Habit’’ in The Principles of Psychology, The Works of William James,19 volumes (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1975–1988), 1890. For Gramsci’s discussion of common sense, see Prison Notebooks, 325–35.

526

CRITICAL PRAGMATISM

In order to understand the shortcomings of pragmatism, says Gramsci, one must take into account the Anglo-Saxon cultural and historical context from which it emerged. Although Gramsci argues that philosophy must be understood as a political enterprise, he finds the pragmatist approach to be steeped in a tradition of vulgar utilitarianism.20 The pragmatists’ focus on the political dimensions of everyday experience is, for Gramsci, correct but insufficiently mediated by critical reflection. While the great virtue of pragmatism is precisely its understanding of human agency as something developed through social interaction, this relationship between experience and agency is too narrowly conceived.21 Quoting an Italian translation of William James’s ‘‘The Variety of Religious Experience,’’ Gramsci argues that pragmatists correctly identify the importance of human agency, but fail to tie this agency to criticism.22 Therefore, pragmatists are unable to identify hegemonic structures at work in the generation of common sense and instead ‘‘judge immediate reality, often at the most vulgar level.’’23 In contrast, the continental tradition is steeped in a desire to ‘‘raise this existing cultural level’’ and has, as a result, produced more genuinely ‘‘practical’’ thinkers by virtue of their philosophical depth. Therefore, argues Gramsci, whereas ‘‘Hegel can be considered the theoretical precursor of the democratic revolutions of the nineteenth century, the pragmatists, at the most, have contributed to the creation of the Rotary Club movement and to the justification of conservative and reactionary movements.’’24 Although Gramsci does not directly tie his criticisms of pragmatism to his fleeting discussions of positivism, the relationship between the two is implicitly established in his argument that pragmatism is a philosophy best suited to buttressing the status quo.25 Because Gramsci’s attack on positivism was aimed at the Orthodox Marxist approaches to scientism in the late 1920s, a more thorough 20. It should be noted that this criticism of pragmatism is alive and well today. See Christopher Lasch, The True and Only Heaven: Progress and its Critics, (New York: Norton, 1991); and John Patrick Diggins, The Promise of Pragmatism (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1994). 21. The distinction Gramsci makes between the Factory Council Movement and the struggle of labor unions best captures his disdain for pragmatism. According to Gramsci, labor unions cannot effect real social change because they treat the worker as a mere wage earner. In contrast, Factory Councils treat workers as members of a productive community, and are therefore able to cultivate a proper relationship between organic and traditional intellectuals in the factory itself. Whereas labor unions can only marginally improve existing conditions in the factory, the Council Movement is about to reconstruct the factory as the nucleus of the future proletarian state. For Gramsci, pragmatists can only form labor unions, while the philosophy of praxis is aimed at fomenting the more properly revolutionary Council Movements. 22. There are no references to Dewey or Peirce in The Prison Notebooks, and so it is unclear whether or not Gramsci read either. 23. Gramsci, Prison Notebooks, 372. 24. Gramsci, Prison Notebooks, 373. 25. Both positivism and pragmatism, according to Gramsci, are blindly infatuated with anything immediately given, thus they are natural allies.

Alison Kadlec

527

conflation of positivism and pragmatism had to await the Frankfurt School’s emigration to the U.S. in the 1930s. While nearly all of the early critical theorists took aim at pragmatism at one point or another, it is particularly in the work of Max Horkheimer that the most devastating misappropriations of Dewey’s pragmatism were developed and situated firmly within the tradition of critical theory.26

From Gramsci to Horkheimer: Pragmatism Reviled In his now-classic history of the Frankfurt School, Martin Jay notes that a significant element of the Frankfurt School theorists’ hostility toward American pragmatism may be traced to the comparatively warmer reception the Vienna Circle was given in the U.S. during the period of their common emigration.27 Richard Bernstein also notes that while logical positivism did not take deep hold in America, a ‘‘positivist temper and the legacy of logical empiricism did flourish.’’ The ascension of analytic philosophy underscored those divisions between American and Continental philosophy that Gramsci had noted two decades earlier and there emerged at this time, particularly in figures such as W.V.O. Quine, expressions of natural affinities between positivism and pragmatism.28 In his earlier assaults on logical positivism, Horkheimer argued that the critically inspired and dynamic elements of empiricism had been completely undermined by the positivist ‘‘abdication of reflection,’’ which resulted in the fetishization of ‘‘facts’’ given immediately in the existing order. Although there is nothing particularly surprising or novel about this attack on positivism, Horkheimer’s pointed and sustained attack on pragmatism must be understood in the context of this critical rejection of positivism. As the locus of these connections, Horkheimer’s 1947 Eclipse of Reason represents his most sustained attempt to recast pragmatism as nothing more than the philosophical residue of positivism. Eclipse of Reason embodies a remarkably clear argument, developed in large part as an explicit attack on Dewey’s particular brand of pragmatism. The work traces the decline of reason as an emancipatory human faculty grounded in objectivity, and the resulting ascendancy of positivism with its narrowly quantitative approach to reason. For my purposes, this is perhaps the clearest example of the Frankfurt School’s conflation of positivism with pragmatism as a philosophical approach. In early 26. It is not clear whether or not Gramsci read Dewey, but Horkheimer certainly did. For similar attacks on pragmatism, see Marcuse’s Reason and Revolution (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1941) and One Dimensional Man (Boston: Beacon Press, 1964). 27. Martin Jay, Dialectical Imagination, 297. 28. Richard Bernstein, ‘‘Pragmatism, Pluralism, and the Healing of Wounds,’’ reprinted in Pragmatism: A Reader, ed. and intro. Louis Menand (New York: Vintage, 1997), 391.

528

CRITICAL PRAGMATISM

modern thought, argues Horkheimer, the sort of empiricism advanced by John Locke had carried with it a conception of reason grounded in critical discernment and reflection. However, with the rise of scientific rationality, reason was severed from the higher claims of objective truth and was reduced instead to the exclusive service of subjective means/ends calculations.29 According to Horkheimer, the birth of pragmatism cannot be understood apart from the ascendancy of positivism: ‘‘Pragmatism has from its beginnings implicitly justified the current substitution of the logic of probability for that of truth. To this kind of philosophy prediction is the essence not only of calculation but of all thinking as such.’’ Whereas reason had once furnished us with the ability to challenge existing structures of domination, be they authoritarian religions or feudal economic relations, the ascendancy of positivism reduced the scope of philosophical reflection to the anemic offerings of pragmatism. For Horkheimer, While philosophy in its objectivist stage sought to be the agency that brought human conduct, including scientific undertakings, to a final understanding of its own reason and justice, pragmatism tries to retranslate any understanding into mere conduct. Its ambition is to be itself nothing else but practical activity, as distinct from theoretical insight, which, according to pragmatistic teachings, is either only a name for physical events or just meaningless. In other words, in exiling objective reason, pragmatism is capable of merely providing the calculations by which the existing order may be legitimized. For Horkheimer, pragmatism not only lacks ‘‘philosophical pedigree,’’ but it is also tantamount to a philosophical apology for all things given. Although Horkheimer refers to James and Peirce, it is Dewey who represents the greatest obstacle to the recovery of critical reflection.30 As the progenitor of the ‘‘most radical and consistent brand of pragmatism,’’ Dewey represents the clearest nexus of positivism and pragmatism, according to Horkheimer. Given his ardor for the natural sciences, Dewey is the pragmatist responsible for the final reduction of human experience to the scientific experiment. Whereas reason had once aimed to overshoot existing structures, thus allowing us to imagine a better possible world, pragmatism can only evaluate existing reality according to its capacities for efficiency, expediency, and predictability. For Horkheimer, Dewey’s positivist call for the unity of sciences ‘‘is the counterpart of modern industrialism, for which the factory is the prototype of human existence, and which models all branches of culture after production on the conveyer belt, or after the rationalized front office.’’31 As philosophy is drained 29. Max Horkheimer, The Eclipse of Reason (New York: Continuum Press, 1947), 5. 30. Horkheimer, Eclipse, 48, 71. 31. Horkheimer, Eclipse, 50.

Alison Kadlec

529

of critical purpose, most notably historical sense and self-reflection, reason is necessarily and hopelessly debased. Pragmatism represents, in short, the philosophical propagation of all modern forms of domination that result from this decline of reason. In the absence of historical perspective and self-awareness, individual pragmatists are ‘‘liberal, tolerant, optimistic, and quite unable to deal with the cultural debacle of our days,’’ while pragmatism, as a philosophy, ‘‘reflects with an almost disarming candor the spirit of the prevailing business culture.’’32 Horkheimer’s argument in Eclipse of Reason is an excellent representation of the hostilities of the early critical theorists toward pragmatism, and captures some enduring features of these hostilities as they have filtered through time to the present. Although the strict association of pragmatism with positivism began to decline with Rorty’s recovery of pragmatism in the late 1970s, the themes celebrated in this recovery underscore the view of pragmatism as a thin philosophy of antifoundational bourgeois liberalism. In a sense, Rorty’s celebration of Dewey mirrors Horkheimer’s rejections; whereas Horkheimer associates pragmatic antifoundationalism with a flimsy apology for all things given, Rorty associates pragmatic antifoundationalism with a blessed liberation from all things dogmatic. Despite the fact that Rorty is an undeniable background figure in any discussion of Dewey, what is important for my purposes is to hold up Horkheimer’s rejection of pragmatism against Dewey’s own account of the philosophic meaning and nature of pragmatism. In doing so, it becomes easier to understand that the early critical theorists’ misrepresentations were passed to their intellectual heirs. Because my specific concern here is with Horkheimer’s view of pragmatism as a philosophy that jettisons reason and reflection, there is no better place to turn than to Dewey’s critical intellectual history of the relationship between reason and experience in Reconstruction in Philosophy.33

Reconstructing Philosophy: Reuniting Reason and Experience Beginning as a series of lectures given in Japan in 1919, and prefigured in his introduction to Essays in Experimental Logic in 1917, the text that later 32. Horkheimer, Eclipse, 85. 33. It is interesting to note that Reconstruction in Philosophy was the text that first attracted the young Marxist, Sidney Hook, to pragmatism. Hook described Reconstruction in Philosophy as ‘‘a brilliant application of the principles of historical materialism,’’ and argued that Dewey, although he did not consider himself a Marxist, ‘‘tried to show in detail how social stratification and class struggles got expressed in the metaphysical dualisms of the time. . . .’’ See Out of Step: An Unquiet Life in the Twentieth Century (New York: Harper & Row, 1987), 81.

530

CRITICAL PRAGMATISM

became Reconstruction in Philosophy signifies the most public pronouncement of a set of ideas that Dewey began developing in the 1880s and 1890s.34 These ideas emerged in the context of Dewey’s larger efforts to trace what he viewed as a noxious strain in Western philosophy, a strain which had afflicted philosophy with latent but persistent antidemocratic tendencies35 Dewey’s intellectual history of Western philosophy yielded a narrative that Robert Westbrook aptly summarizes as ‘‘the story of an inevitably unsuccessful pursuit by philosophers of a therapeutic quest for absolutely certain knowledge of truth, goodness, and beauty in an unavoidably contingent world.’’36 Although Dewey admired the Greeks, he argued that Plato and Aristotle, each in his own way, ‘‘translated into rational form the doctrine of escape from the vicissitudes of existence by means of measures which do not demand an active coping with conditions.’’37 The deleterious consequences of this escapism, says Dewey, must be understood if we are to reconstruct philosophy for democratic purposes. In his introduction to Reconstruction in Philosophy, published some 25 years after the original work, Dewey clarified the key point of his historical approach to philosophy; contemporary society has inherited from classical philosophy a set of dualisms that must be exposed and dismantled if we are to make real progress toward improving the human condition in an age of industrialization and world war. Dewey undertakes the task of exposing what he sees as the unfortunate consequences of the bifurcation of reason from experience in the work of the classical philosophers. He argues that classical philosophers, in seeking to preserve the threatened beliefs of a fading tradition, attempted to cast their own interests as ultimate truths. In attempting to anchor traditional forms of authority under conditions of social flux, the Ancients demanded a normative and final distinction between Truth-yielding Reason and mere experience. Reason, ‘‘which in its metaphysical rendering became the world of the highest and ultimate reality,’’ was thus placed in a position to debase, subjugate, and thereby discipline the other ‘‘ordinary empirical’’ realm of everyday experience. The result was that philosophy, from the classical age forward, ‘‘has arrogated to itself the office

34. See ‘‘Ethics and Physical Science’’ (EW1), and ‘‘Reconstruction’’ (EW4). 35. This effort to deploy historical investigation in exposing obstacles to democracy began quite early in Dewey’s career and culminated in The Quest for Certainty (LW4). 36. Westbrook, John Dewey, 348. 37. The Quest for Certainty (LW4: 20). Dewey’s appreciation of classical Greek philosophy owed a great deal to the early influence of G.S. Morris and the later influence of F.J.E. Woodbridge. In addition to The Quest for Certainty and Reconstruction and Philosophy, see Dewey’s ‘‘The ‘Socratic Dialogues’ of Plato’’ (LW2: 124–40). For an excellent discussion of Dewey’s complex ambivalence toward Aristotle and Plato, and his subsequent appraisal of classical philosophy at the start of the 1920s, see Westbrook, John Dewey, 347–61.

Alison Kadlec

531

of demonstrating the existence of a transcendent, absolute or inner reality and of revealing to man the nature and features of this ultimate and higher reality.’’38 In turn, the everyday lived experience has been relegated to the lowly and unenlightening position of mere experience and cannot, therefore, be a viewed as a legitimate or authoritative resource for critical reflection. Dewey argues that the divarication of reason and experience is especially troubling because it derived in part from a distortion that served to mask particular entrenched interests. Moreover, the crimes of the Ancients exceed their specific context because historical perspective reveals that this false dualism has been passed to us in the form of a decidedly antidemocratic inability to give full credit to the role of experience in the exercise of reason as a critical faculty.39 Alan Ryan, in his excellent treatment of Dewey’s ambivalence toward Plato and Artistotle, emphasizes the extent to which class interests figured into Dewey’s indictment of dualistic thinking. Dewey was aware, says Ryan, that ‘‘a society in which the grinding hard work was done by slaves, or by a lower class excluded from politics, was always in danger of associating thinking with high status and doing with low status and thus of projecting its own snobberies into the universe and receiving them back as metaphysics.’’40 As the classical philosophers debased lived experience, the power to criticize existing institutions and arrangements was essentially taken out of the realm of ordinary people’s lives, while those who had a vested interest in maintaining the status quo had recourse to the ‘‘transcendent and ultimate realm’’ to buttress their authority.41 The implication of this prioritizing split is that Reason became a remote realm, accessible only to the elite few, while the more properly democratic realm of lived experience was 38. Dewey, Reconstruction, 91–92. 39. Although I take up Dewey’s notion of ‘‘experience’’ in more detail in subsequent sections, it is important to clarify here that Dewey’s vibrant and transformatory view of experience stands in stark contrast to the Ancient Greek view of experience as the ordinary and unreflective realm in which we privately absorb the given stimulus of everyday life. Likewise, as an intersubjective, communicative, and social medium that is grounded in the back-and-forth movement between reflection and forwardthinking perception of consequences, Dewey’s view is radically different from the positivist notion of experience as mere sense-perception. 40. Alan Ryan, John Dewey and the High Tide of American Liberalism (New York: W.W. Norton and Company, 1995), 98. While any simplistic notion of ‘‘class struggle’’ would be regarded by Dewey as coming dangerously close to generating yet another noxious dualism (‘‘oppressor’’/‘‘oppressed’’), it is nonetheless true that he was deeply concerned with the ways in which failure to grasp the democratic possibilities of experience plays a part in the discursive construction of iniquities. The most explicit and concrete expression of this concern is found in Dewey’s discussions of education, and in his particular struggle against a dual system of vocational education that gained momentum during the first decades of the twentieth century. In this context, Dewey occasionally deployed the language of class struggle to distinguish his social democratic view of education from the prevailing view of education. See ‘‘Education from a Social Perspective’’ (MW7: 113–27). Also see Chap. 19 of Democracy and Education (MW9) for Dewey’s explicit discussion of the relationship between class oppression in Ancient Greece and the inherited labor/leisure dualism undergirding the call for a dual system of vocational education. 41. Dewey, Reconstruction, 91–93.

532

CRITICAL PRAGMATISM

sapped of it power to inform or guide critical reflection. As the few made themselves the sole guardians of truth, the many lost the footing from which a challenge to dominant norms and practices might have been launched. By exposing the interests at work in the construction of classical dualisms, Dewey engages in a type of social criticism that is aimed both at exposing fraudulent interests lurking beneath the surface in classical philosophy and at producing the conditions for greater enlightenment among the inheritors of the classical legacy. Using the traditional vernacular of critical theory, one could say that Dewey’s intellectual history of philosophy is aimed at enabling agents to distinguish between real and false interests. In other words, Dewey’s attempt to expose the elitist interest in tradition-preservation at the core of the Ancients’ bifurcation of reason and experience is properly critical because it reveals the ‘‘mobilization of bias’’ and the disciplinary function involved in appeals to ultimate Reason.42 By reconstructing the power of lived experience to inform critical reflection, Dewey engages in a type of trenchant social criticism that is akin to the emancipatory interest-oriented analyses of traditional critical theorists. The crucial difference, however, is that it is an antifoundational disposition that undergirds Dewey’s hostility toward dualistic constructs. Although Dewey’s elevation of experience as a critical resource does not necessarily mean that lived experience must or will serve progressive purposes, it is precisely this potential that motivated Dewey’s pedagogical commitments and political struggles throughout his life. Arguing that the reason/experience split was passed to us in the form of the leisure/labor and thinking/doing dichotomies, Dewey argues that a democracy cannot thrive under such debilitating constructs. In fact, he says, ‘‘the price that democratic societies will have to pay for their continuing health is the elimination of an oligarchy that attempts to monopolize the benefits of intelligence and of the best methods for the profit of a few privileged ones. . .’’43 Refusing to accept the dichotomies that pit reason against experience, and thought against action, puts us on the right path in this battle, because a reconstruction of experience is an integral component of democratic struggle. In contrast to a narrowly conceived notion of experience as a matter of immediacy or mere sense-perception, Dewey’s robust notion of experience is imbued with critical social force. As the intersubjective, social, and communicative medium from which knowledge springs, lived experience is both the source and the 42. I borrow the phrase ‘‘mobilization of bias’’ from Steven Lukes here to underscore the extent to which Dewey’s analysis is grounded in his attention to power relations. While my discussion of the Ancient Greeks’ use of power to buttress the status quo is aimed at exposing power relations, I do not mean to imply any vulgar or simplistic or dualistic notion of ‘‘class struggle.’’ See Power: A Radical View (London: Macmillan Press, 1974). 43. ‘‘Education From a Social Perspective’’ (MW7: 127).

Alison Kadlec

533

product of reflective reason.44 Further, because experience is a back and forth process of perceiving and adjusting to the consequences of our actions, it is ‘‘a future implicated in a present’’ and therefore replete with experimental and democratic possibilities. From this perspective, dismantling the dualisms that protect what Dewey calls the ‘‘orthodox description of experience’’ is required in order to reveal the democratic potential residing in a more dynamic and social conception of experience. Not only is Dewey’s notion of experience ‘‘more congenial to present conditions,’’ it is also a powerful resource for the development of our capacities for free inquiry and critical reflection.45 Given Dewey’s democratic commitments, the question is how do we actualize the critical potential of everyday experience and transform it into an active reservoir for social change? Although Dewey was famously elusive when it came to providing hard and fast answers, the most important clues may be found in Dewey’s celebration of the scientific enterprise. Out of his persistent and contentious admiration of science, Dewey developed a morally charged idea of ‘‘growth’’ that serves as the linchpin of his commitment to lived experience as a repository for critical reflection. Moreover, it is from this unique conception of ‘‘growth’’ as a moral imperative that Dewey undertakes a reconstruction of ‘‘individualism’’ aimed at fulfilling the critical promise of experience for democratic struggle. Dewey’s antifoundational enthusiasm for a scientific worldview is the context in which this nexus of experience, growth, individualism, social intelligence, and meaningful democratic struggle must be understood. Therefore, it is only by turning to the role of science in Dewey’s view of reconstruction that we may begin to trace the contours of this complex matrix.46

Science and Reconstruction: Experience as Social, Dynamic, and Reflective In Reconstruction in Philosophy science plays a crucial role in Dewey’s desire to reconstruct the relationship between reason and experience, and if we look closely at Dewey’s celebration of science we find that it is not of the sort that Horkheimer maintains. Dewey’s enthusiasm for the scientific method is not grounded in a positivistic desire for verification of objective facts or for prediction and control, although he does maintain that science affords us greater control of 44. See Experience and Nature for Dewey’s discussion of the primacy of experience in the development of knowledge (LW1:27–28). 45. ‘‘The Need for a Recovery of Philosophy’’ (MW10: 8–9). 46. For an especially good discussion of the failures of positivism, see Chap. 10 of The Quest for Certainty (LW4).

534

CRITICAL PRAGMATISM

the elements determining our condition. Nor is Dewey’s approach to science a vulgar or reductionist glorification of all things given, as Horkheimer and Gramsci would argue. For Dewey, science releases us from a fixed and static conception of the world, and presents in its place a dynamic world that is always in-the-making, always changing, ever open, and ‘‘so multiplex and far-reaching’’ that it cannot be contained in any cramped metaphysical vision that sets Reason over and above the world as it is experienced in everyday life. Horkheimer’s claim that pragmatism cannot be understood apart from the advent of the scientific revolution is absolutely correct. It is, however, the meaning of this relationship that Horkheimer and a multitude of subsequent thinkers have misconstrued. Although the intricacies of Dewey’s enthusiasm for science could, and does, fill volumes, it is enough here to say that one key to understanding the role of science in Dewey’s critical philosophy of pragmatism is located in the influence of Darwin on Dewey’s thought.47 For example, Dewey’s short and remarkably lucid ‘‘The Influence of Darwin on Philosophy’’ (1909) serves as an important backdrop to many of the themes he developed a decade later in Reconstruction in Philosophy. In particular, the idea of philosophy as a problem-centered enterprise, the importance of change rather than permanence, the emphasis on consequences rather than absolute Truths, and the celebration of process rather than the search for final ends are all deftly touched upon in this article. According to Dewey, the publication of On the Origin of Species performed the timely and much needed service of ‘‘laying hands upon the sacred ark of absolute permanency’’ and, in doing so, opened the door for a transformation in ‘‘the logic of knowledge, and hence the treatment of morals, politics, and religion.’’48 In short, the intellectual transformation effected by Darwinian thought represents a shift in the sorts of questions we are able to find interesting; we are free to forgo questions of who or what made the world, in favor of questions about what kind of world it is and may become.49 47. The influence of Darwin’s work on Dewey was profound, and it has been either misunderstood or merely overlooked. As Louis Menand notes, the world that Darwin described was one governed by contingency, process, random chance, and openness, and it was out of this world that Dewey himself grew and developed as a philosopher of ‘‘continued investigation, experiment, hermeneutic openness, provisional conclusions, and social progress.’’ See Louis Menand, The Metaphysical Club (New York: Farrar, Strauss, and Giroux, 2001), 121; and Jay Martin, The Education of John Dewey (New York: Columbia University Press, 2002), 253. It must also be noted that Dewey went to great lengths to distinguish his holistic and progressive evolutionary perspective from those of vulgar social Darwinists such as Herbert Spencer. For excellent treatments of the conceptual and moral poverty of Spencer’s conception of ‘‘survival of the fittest’’, see Dewey’s ‘‘Ethics and Physical Science’’ (EW1) and ‘‘Evolution and Ethics’’ (EW5). 48. ‘‘The Influence of Darwin on Philosophy’’ (MW4: 3). 49. This is akin to Foucault’s understanding of truth. As Paul Rabinow notes in his comparison of Chomsky and Foucault, the latter is less interested in identifying the truth than in exploring what functions are performed by truth claims. This shift from ‘‘what’’ to ‘‘how’’ is very much like the shift that Dewey sees initiated by Darwin. See The Foucault Reader (New York: Pantheon Books, 1984), 12.

Alison Kadlec

535

For the Greeks, human experience was confined to the realm of custom, over and above which Reason had to stand as the ultimate redeemer. With the scientific revolution, however, this relationship undergoes a peculiar reversal; experience becomes a central focus of scientific inquiry, while ‘‘Reason and its bodyguard of general notions is now the conservative mind-enslaving factor.’’ As a consequence, appeals to universal Truth begin ‘‘to strike us as remote, uninteresting and unimportant.’’ In other words, we are indebted to the scientific revolution because its unfolding revealed that reason does not occupy a realm apart from experience, and intelligence is not something possessed once and for all. Instead, both reason and intelligence are aspects of a process, a process that can only be comprehended in experience. Whereas Horkheimer argues that this elevation of experience over abstract appeals to Reason represents a crude justification of the status quo, Dewey argues the reverse. In contrast to an experimental and readjusting intelligence, the old idea of Reason originated in specific entrenched interests and has resulted in irresponsible rigidity and negligent vanity.50 In letting go of absolutes, we do not abandon our convictions or surrender our capacity for critical reflection. Instead, says Dewey, ‘‘when the belief that knowledge is active and operative takes hold of men, the ideal realm is no longer aloof and separate; it is rather that collection of imagined possibilities that stimulates men to new efforts and realizations.’’ Philosophically speaking, reuniting reason and experience does not diminish the dignity of philosophy by knocking it from its speculative pedestal and replacing it with gross utilitarianism. Rather, it elevates experience and signifies that the prime function of philosophy is that of working toward realizing the possibilities of experience as a social and dynamic medium for critical reflection. From this perspective, Dewey’s approach to the relationship between experience and reason has more in common with Gramsci’s philosophy of praxis than with Bentham’s utilitarianism. In contrast to both Gramsci’s and Horkheimer’s characterizations of pragmatism as vulgar utilitarianism, Dewey argues that, ‘‘if utilitarianism did not actively promote the new economic materialism, it had no means of combating it. In spite of its interest in a thoroughly social aim, utilitarianism fostered a new class interest, that of the capitalist property-owning interests.’’51 For Dewey, if we overlook the social functions involved in all enterprises of knowing, then we lose the critical capacity to identify distortions in communication that serve specific antidemocratic interests.52 In other words, inquiry 50. Dewey, Reconstruction, 133–34. 51. Dewey, Reconstruction, 150. 52. See ‘‘The Inclusive Philosophical Idea’’ (LW3) for a great discussion of Dewey’s view of ‘‘the social’’ as a linchpin for any effective critical philosophy. For Dewey, ‘‘the social’’ is a construct deployed to capture the intersubjective and communicative dimensions of philosophy as a critical enterprise, and,

536

CRITICAL PRAGMATISM

loses its critical purpose and we lose the ability to identify the power at work when particular interests masquerade as epistemological truths. Under these conditions, the democratic potential of a socially conceived notion of experience is eclipsed and, as a result, our capacity to develop the sorts of habits required for the pursuit of democratic goals is effectively curtailed. In fact, says Dewey, ‘‘the barriers to free inquiry are so many and so solid that mankind is to be congratulated that the very act of investigation is capable of itself becoming a delightful and absorbing pursuit.’’ Contrary to the views advanced by the early critical theorists, we are not released from social obligations because we relinquish our ultimate, fixed, or final standards of moral judgment. In fact, says Dewey, our obligation to battle all barriers to freedom of inquiry and expression are only deepened because they become a matter of addressing the real conditions of peoples’ lives. Like Gramsci, Dewey breaks down the division between politics and philosophy by arguing that the political responsibility to critically engage lived experience is itself a philosophical matter. Moreover, it is the social purpose of philosophy that gives pragmatism its normative meaning and moral force. Our social arrangements and institutions should not be viewed as the means for obtaining things for individuals. Instead, they are the ‘‘means of creating individuals,’’ and thus individuality is itself ‘‘something to be wrought out’’ in social life.53 This view of the individual is, I argue, profoundly critical and can only be understood in the context of Dewey’s broader views on the relationship between ‘‘growth,’’ social intelligence, and democracy.

Reconstructing Individualism: Growth and the Critical Purpose of Philosophy In Reconstruction in Philosophy, ‘‘growth’’ is the linchpin of Dewey’s democratic commitments to lived experience. Dewey’s understanding of meaningful democracy is intimately connected to his understanding of ‘‘growth’’ as the only genuinely moral goal of any society. In declaring that growth is the only moral end, Dewey characteristically avoids a substantive definition of the word, and this refusal to pin a final meaning on his use of ‘‘growth’’ raises some troubling questions: If growth is to be generally celebrated, does this mean that any sort of growth is to be valued? If so, how are we to understand the varieties of growth that are deleterious to individuals and society? For example, within the social sciences, ‘‘growth’’ is often associated with unfettered capitalism or explosions as such, it should not be confused with Arendt’s use of the term. See Hanna Fenichel Pitkin’s Attack of the Blob: Hannah Arendt’s Concept of the Social (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988). 53. Dewey, Reconstruction, 150.

Alison Kadlec

537

in population, and this is to say nothing of the troubling connotations the word ‘‘growth’’ carries in the medical sciences. For Dewey, growth cannot be conflated with any unspecified or generic conception of expansion. Growth is not to be understood as expansion, unless that which is expanding the capacity for critical inquiry, or in Dewey’s words ‘‘the method of intelligence.’’ Moreover, like the idea of experience, growth implies a reciprocal relationship between the expansion of social intelligence and the goods generated by these means. To grow, according to Dewey, is both to increase an individual’s capacity for social intelligence and to translate that capacity into the generation of concrete goods. In other words, growth is simultaneously the goal and the process, the critical standard and the product of social intelligence. Social intelligence, in turn, is a concept that must be understood in the context of Dewey’s critical reconstruction of individualism. Dewey’s brief statements regarding the relationship between philosophy, education, and democracy as put forth in Reconstruction in Philosophy help to shed light on this idea of growth, as well as the critical status of experience in pragmatism: Government, business, art, religion, all social institutions have a meaning, a purpose. That purpose is to set free and to develop the capacities of human individuals without respect to race, sex, class or economic status. And this is all one with saying that the test of their value is the extent to which they educate every individual into the full stature of his possibility. Democracy has many meanings, but if it has a moral meaning, it is found in resolving that the supreme test of all political institutions and industrial arrangements shall be the contribution they make to the all-around growth of every member of society.54 Democracy, then, cannot be reduced to a set of institutional functions or abstract visions of the state. Institutions must be evaluated according to their educative function, and for Dewey this means that institutions must be judged according to the sorts of individuals they cultivate. Although Dewey does not focus his attention in Reconstruction in Philosophy on delineating the conditions for the cultivation of individuals who are capable of critical social intelligence, he was not blind to such matters. In fact, much of Dewey’s work in the 1920s and 1930s was aimed at creating a picture of the sorts of habits required for a full release of the critical potential of lived experience. In Individualism Old and New (1929), Dewey argues explicitly for a reconstructed notion of individuality that is consistent with his principle of growth as the expansion of the individual’s capacity for free inquiry, social intelligence, and critical reflection. In this, and 54. Dewey, Reconstruction, 186.

538

CRITICAL PRAGMATISM

many other works of this period, Dewey argues that we have inherited from an earlier epoch a conception of the individual which is not consonant with our contemporary conditions, and the result of this inheritance is the perpetuation of an undemocratic mindset and its attending institutions. The heart of the problem is that individuals are wrongly conceptualized in isolation from one another, and individualism is speciously conflated with atomistic and antagonistic independence. Despite the fact that we live in a profoundly collective world, our inherited image of the individual has created a contemporary situation in which we are unable to perceive our shared interests or the consequences of our collective existence. We are educated into a system that views individuals as competitive and antagonistic, when in fact we live in a world of inescapable interdependence. This dissonance has potentially disastrous consequences, because the ongoing failure to apprehend the shared consequences of our individual choices can become a mortal threat to our most deeply held commitments to liberty and equality of opportunity. For Dewey, the effects of this bankrupt conception of atomistic individualism cascade through every level of society, revealing structures of domination and distortions of communication all along the way. In being educated by a discourse of rugged individualism which places the highest value on individual pecuniary gain and competition, we are the manipulated products of a ‘‘mental and moral corporateness for which history affords no parallel,’’ and ‘‘live exposed to the greatest flood of mass suggestion that any people has ever experienced.’’55 The result of this pecuniary individualism is a crushing conformity of public opinion that cripples citizens’ abilities to identify, much less understand, real shared interests and when those interests are being undermined. In the absence of an ability to perceive the consequences of our collective existence, no meaningful individualism can flourish, and no real democracy can be cultivated. In fact, ‘‘one cannot imagine a bitterer comment on any professed individualism than that it subordinated the only creative individuality—that of mind—to the perpetuation of an unjust and morally impoverished regime of pecuniary gain.’’56 In bold

55. Although it is only in the later Liberalism and Social Action (LW11) that Dewey focuses explicitly on the extent to which entrenched economic interests directly benefit from a perpetuation of this fraudulent conception of the individual as an isolated, acquisitive entity, Individualism Old and New (LW5) does represent the first step in that direction. 56. Dewey, Individualism Old and New, (LW5:59, 85). Dewey’s concern with the ‘‘subordination of creative individuality’’ places him in the company of other thinkers, most notably J.S. Mill and Alexis de Tocqueville who have been, each in his own way, preoccupied with the tendency in modern society toward regimentation of thought and opinion. For Mill, this ‘‘despotism of custom is everywhere the standing hindrance to human advancement,’’ and for Tocqueville, the power of public opinion in America is such that it ‘‘brings immense weight to bear on every individual. It surrounds, directs, and oppresses him.’’ J.S. Mill, On Liberty (London: Everyman’s Press, 1972), 138; Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, ed. J.P. Mayer, trans. George Lawrence (New York: Harper and Row), 643.

Alison Kadlec

539

statements such as these, Dewey reveals the extent to which his vision of a vital public and a meaningful democracy provides the tools for critical interrogation of existing institutions. Just as contemporary critical theorists look beyond vulgar materialism to instead focus on the discursive manipulation of interests, Dewey argues, ‘‘the educative influence of economic and political institutions is, in the last analysis, even more important than their immediate economic consequences. The mental poverty that comes from one-sided distortion of mind is ultimately more significant than poverty in material goods.’’57 The critical purchase of Dewey’s understanding of individuality here is located in his hope for a new type of individualism that is communicative, imaginative, and critical, rather than atomistic, acquisitive, and antagonistic. Reconstructing our understanding of individualism is of paramount importance for Dewey, because it is only through a conscious commitment to the cultivation of habits of social intelligence that we will be able to reverse the antidemocratic tide. Contrary to Gramsci’s, Horkhiemer’s, and now White’s claims that pragmatism does not contain sufficient normative force because it fails to appeal to an objective notion of ‘‘real interests,’’ Dewey responds that the development of individuals who possess habits of critical intelligence and the capacity to engage in shared inquiry and communication ‘‘are the only actual ways of universalizing the moral law and end.’’58 For Dewey, if we do not undertake a pragmatic reconstructing of philosophy, aimed at recovering lived experience as a socially dynamic reservoir for critical reflection, we will be unable to understand, much less expose, systemic patterns of injustice and inequality plaguing our past, present, and foreseeable future. As it stands now, in the absence of such a pragmatic reconstruction of philosophy, The region of concrete difficulties where the assistance of intelligent method for the tentative plans for experimentation is urgently needed is precisely where intelligence fails to operate. In this region of the specific and the concrete, men are thrown back upon the crudest empiricism, upon shortsighted opportunism and the matching of brute forces. For Dewey, the ‘‘growth’’ of individuals imbued with the habits of social intelligence and critical reflection is itself a real interest. From this perspective, Dewey’s lifelong commitment to improving the conditions of early childhood education takes on greater political significance. Releasing the critical potential of lived experience requires, first and foremost, that we rethink the purpose and meaning of our educational practices. Because democracy concerns far more than institutional mechanisms for Dewey, 57. Dewey, Individualism, 103. 58. Dewey, Reconstruction, 190, 197.

540

CRITICAL PRAGMATISM

education must also entail a great deal more than the formal schooling which prepares us to occupy our proper and productive places in society. Education, says Dewey, does not prepare us for anything, it is rather the process by which we ‘‘grow’’ and develop as self-directing human beings capable of recognizing the consequences of our actions and, as a result, become capable of effecting change toward the betterment of our collective existence. For Dewey, education is ‘‘a process of living and not a preparation for future living’’ that receives its moral content through its connection with social life. Dewey most clearly makes the argument that proper education, as a matter of morality, can only take place in a social context in his statement that, Much of the present education fails because it neglects this fundamental principle of the school as a form of community life. . . . I believe that moral education centers about this conception of the school as a mode of social life, that the best and deepest moral training is precisely that which one gets through having to enter into proper relations with others in a unity of work and thought.59 In other words, moral and ethical considerations are important only insofar as they are connected to the continual growth and of social life, or associated living. For Dewey, there is no individual morality apart from social context and, therefore, education must be anchored by the principle that individual intelligence is a process of social growth. Not only must we revamp the way we treat childhood educational institutions, we must also provide the opportunities for real growth of creative intelligence for all adults as well. By improving habits of communication, we can rethink the meaning of individualism along more fully democratic lines. Opening paths for this sort of reconstruction of individualism can, in turn, help us realize the critical potential of lived experience as that which funds creative social intelligence.

Conclusion When Alain Locke warned in 1935 that, ‘‘we must take care not to exile our imperatives, for after all, we live by them,’’ he went straight to the heart of the problems that accompany any undertaking that might call itself ‘‘critical pragmatism.’’ How is it that we can reject all absolutes and yet retain the normative force required for anchoring our critical judgments? In short, how might a philosophy of critical pragmatism be both pragmatic and critical? My

59. Dewey, Reconstruction, 93.

Alison Kadlec

541

efforts here have been aimed at opening avenues of inquiry into this question by attempting to reconstruct the critical features of Dewey’s pragmatism. By focusing first on the historical dimensions of the relationship between critical theory and pragmatism, I have attempted to demonstrate that a persistent conflation of pragmatism and positivism, along with a foundational rejection of science as vulgar reductionism, has served as an obstacle to recovering Dewey’s pragmatism as a critical social theory. Second, by turning to Dewey’s own historical approach in Reconstruction in Philosophy and Individualism Old and New, I aimed to delineate the critical features of Dewey’s approach to lived experience, growth, individualism, and social intelligence. Although it has not been my intention here to show that Dewey’s pragmatism is a definitive or ‘‘authentic’’ example of a critical theory, I hope to have contributed to closing the epistemological gap between critical theory and pragmatism. Contrary to Gramsci’s spectacular misunderstanding of pragmatism as nothing more than philosophical inspiration for Rotarians, and Horkheimer’s understandable though utterly inaccurate treatment of pragmatism as the philosophical justification of positivism, Dewey’s emphases on growth and social intelligence are grounded in a critical commitment to meaningful democracy. The democratic values of free inquiry and genuine equality of opportunity to develop individual capacities in the context of a community of shared interests are nothing less than real interests. In turn, this critical commitment to these real interests, I have argued, is made possible through Dewey’s antifoundational rejection of dualistic constructs. In other words, Dewey’s emancipatory and interest-oriented social theory is critical because, not in spite, of his antifoundationalism. For critical pragmatists such as Dewey, the point of reflective inquiry is not to generate final principles, but rather to improve our capacity for tapping into the critical potential of lived experience in a world defined by flux and change. The political, social, and economic challenges we face require that we arm ourselves not with fixed absolutes, but rather with a commitment to open-ended and flexible inquiry aimed not at final consensus about our aims, but rather at achieving a greater understanding of the consequences of our practices and policies. Critical pragmatism is instructive in its commitment to building thick connections between individuals, groups, and disciplines for the purpose of expanding understanding of our shared interests. We do not need absolutes of any kind to critically interrogate the antidemocratic interests that are being served by the perpetuation of an antagonistic and pecuniary conception of the individual. Our very real interests in freedom of thought and action are obviously not being served by a prevailing view of the individual that closes off any number of possibilities for experiential and communicative creativity. A reconstructed

542

CRITICAL PRAGMATISM

notion of the relationship between individualism and democracy, consistent with an enlightened conception of the experiential dimensions of social intelligence, is itself the goal. However, the goal is not an end or a destination; it is a process, and the stakes are enormously high. Regardless of the irreducible plurality of our values and the ineradicable contingency of our condition, Dewey helps us remember that ‘‘the only freedom that is of enduring importance is the freedom of intelligence.’’

Suggest Documents